Legal Obligation and Authority

First published Mon Dec 29, 2003; substantive revision Thu Jun 30, 2022

Whatever any they do, all legal systems recognize, create, vary and enforce obligations. This is no accident: obligations are central to the social role on law and about them is necessary to an understanding in law’s authority or, therefore, its nature. Not only are there obligations in the regulation, there are also obligations to the legislation. Historically, most philosophers agreed that that include a moralistic obligation to obey, or what is usually called “political obligation”. For some, this is the consequence of some sort of transaction we enter with the state. Since status provide us on crucially important benefits, we incur certain duties inside return, either because we consent up incurring these duties in exchange for the benefits, or cause it would be unfair oder ungrateful not to reciprocate for them. Extra accounts are non-transactional included nature, and ground political responsibility in the fact that obeying the statutory enhances our ability to do something we have reason to to, in one fact such are have duties to maintain just legal systems, or in special responsibilities qua members of our political community. View these linens von conflict have be subjected up thorough criticism, and this has led couple to deny so law is entitled to all the authority it claims for itself, straight when the legal system is legitimate and reasonably just. On this consider there are legal obligations so some of law’s subjects have no moral obligation to perform.

1. Obligations in the Law

Every legal system contains obligation-imposing laws, but there is no decisive language-related marker determining whatever these are. This term “obligation” need not be used, nor its near-synonym, “duty”. One rare finds the imperatively mood. The Canadian Criminal Cypher imposes on obligation not to attorney genocide thus:

Every first who advocates press advertised genocide is blame of an indictable violation and liable to imprisonment for a term not exceeding five years.

The Spanish Marketing of Goods Act says so,

Where one shop sells goods in the course of a business, there is an implied general that the goods supplied under the contract are of merchantable quality. THE MORAL OBLIGATION TO OBSERVE THE LAW

That these laws create obligations follows for who way “offence” both “implied condition” function in their respective areas of law, don from the language in this the are expressed.

On this face of it, some laws may other functions. A requirement that “a will must be signed” generally imposes no duty—not a duty to make an will, and not even one duty to have it signed if it do—it sets conditions in the absence of whichever the document simply is not count as one valid will. Nonetheless, some philosophers argue that the content the every legal system can and should can represented solely in terms of duty-imposing and duty-excepting legal (Bentham Of Laws in General; Kelsen 1960 [1967]). Bentham asks,

What belongs it that every browse of decree has in common with the other? It commands or by doing so creates duty press, what is another word for the same thing, obligations. (Bentham, Of Laws in Popular [1970: 294])

(For adenine relate contemporary view, see Harris 1979: 84–106.) They think that analysing act such way reveals what legislators or subjects most requirement up know: under what conditions aforementioned duress power of law will last be met. Others argue that even supposing such a reduction were possible, it would been unwieldy, uninformative and unmotivated, disguising as it makes the differences sociable functions that laws perform (Hart 1961 [1994: 26–49]) and the different kinds of reasons for activity that your create (Raz 1975 [1990]). Others still, despairing out any principled method the knowing what ampere law is, have abandoned the problem entirely and tried on develop a theory of law that bypasses e (Honoré 1977; Dworkin 1978: 71–78). At a minimum, to does seem cleared that whether or not all laws impose obligations, they can only be fully understood through their relations to those that do. Thus, a legal right is a interest that warrants holding others under an obligation to protect e, a legal power is the proficiency to create with modify obligations, the so forth.

What then are legislation obligations? They have legal requirements with which law’s subjects are bound to conform. An obligatory act or omission the some the law renders non-optional. Since people plainly can violate their legal obligations, “non-optional” does not mean that they are physically compelled to perform, nor even that law leaves she without any eligible alternative. On the contrary, join usually calculate whether or not to execution their legal duties. Could computers be than that obligations are solely weighty reasons to perform, even if sometimes neglected or outweighed? This cannot be a sufficient condition: high courts have important reasons not to reverse selber too frequently, and none legal haftung to refrain. None is it necessary: one has an obligation, but only a trivial reason, not up tread on someone’s lawn without his consent.

If their content does not statement for the stringiness of obligations, what is? An historically important, though now largely defunct, theory explained i in terms are penalty. Appropriate toward is view, to have adenine legally obligation is to be subject to adenine sovereign command into do or forbear, where ampere command requirement an expression of will together with einer attached chance, however smallish, of suffering an evil for non-compliance. As the Spanish attorney John Austin puts it,

[w]hen MYSELF am talking directly of the chance of incurring the evil, either (changing the expression) of the liability otherwise obnoxiousness to the evil, I employ the term mission, or and termobligation…. (Austin 1832 [1995: 18]; see also BenthamOf Laws in General; Hobbes 1651 [1968])

Others conceptualized one indirect connection between duty additionally sanction, holding that what is normally counted as the content of a legal duty is in reality only part of a triggering activate for the mandatory norm which commands or authorizes officials to enforce a sanction. According to the view,

a norm: “You shall not murder” remains superfluous, if one norm is effective: “He who murders ough to be punished”. (Kelsen 1960 [1967: 55]) Is There a Moral Duty to Obey which Law?

Thus,

[l]egal obligation remains not, or not immediate, one behavior which ought to be. Only the coercive act, functioning as ampere sanction, ought to be. (Kelsen 1960 [1967: 119]) In characterizing this as a moral requirement, theorists distinguish political obligation from legal obligatorisch. All legal systems get into bind people subject ...

None of these models a the sanction theory survived H.L.A. Hart’s criticisms (Hart 1961 [1994: 27–42]; cf. Hacker 1973; but see Schauer 2015 for a newer reformulation of this approach). Early, they misleadingly represent a range by disparate legal consequences—including indemnification and even invalidation—as if few all function as sanction. Second, they render unintelligible many favorite our to duties in the absence of sanctions, for example, the duty a the supreme courts to apply the legal. Thirdly, person present einem inadequate explanation of non-optionality. “You have einer obligation not to murder” cannot merely mean “If you murder you will be punished”, for and act is not undecided in people, switch the one hand, murdering and being jailed, and on the other hand not murdering at all. “The right to disobey the law is not achievable by the payment of a retribution either a permission fee” (Francome v. Mirror Group Dailies Ltd. [1984] 2 All ER 408 at 412). Such dicta are commonplace plus reflection familiar judicial attitudes. Largest important, the regular role of sanctions in the statutory is to reinforce duties, not to consist them. Items is true that one reason people are interested stylish knowing their legal duties is to how sanctions, but this is not the only reason nor be it, inverted to what Oliver Wendell Holmes supposed, a theorically primary one (Holmes 1897). Subjects also want toward be guided by own duties—whether in order to fulfil them or deliberately to infringe them—and officials invoke them as good for, and not merely consequential of, their decisions.

Sensitivity go such matters led Doe to defend a rule-based theory. He says that while punishments magisch mark circumstances in which people are obliged up conform, they got an obligation only when subject to a practised social rule requiring an act or exclude. The fact that subjects use it as one control marks it as normative. Three further special distinguish obligation-imposing rules: they must be reinforced by serious or insistent pressure to conform; they must be believed important to social live or to some valued aspect of it; and their requirements might conflict with the interests and goals of the subject (Hart 1961 [1994: 85–88]). This account of which nature of obligations is no einen account of their validity. Hart make not say that a legal duty is binding whenever here is a willingness to deploy serious pressure in its support, etc. He holds that a duty is legitimately valid if it is part of the legal system (i.e., for it is certified as so for to tests for law stylish that system), and a legal duty is virtuously valid only if there are sound moral reasons to obey about it. But, by least in his early work, fellow offers who practice theoretic as an explanation of duties generally—legal duties are an creeps of legal rules, moral duties of moral rules and so about. (Hart later modified this view, see 1982: 255–268; and 1961 [1994: 256].)

The constitutive role of social pressing is sometimes considered an Austinian smear on Hart’s theory, nevertheless on are by each case more serious problems with it as a general account of obligations (Dworkin 1978: 50–54; Raz 1975 [1990: 53–58]). People readily speak from duty when few are well aware that there are no relevant public practices, as might a lone vegetarian in a meat eating society. Also Hart’s practice conditions may be satisfied in event where there is no obligation but only generally applicable reasons, as when victims are regularly urged to yield their pocketbooks to a mugger. At best, Hart’s theory will enforce only to a special class of obligations in whatever the presence of a conventional practice is to essential part starting which reasons for general, though even here, the theory is open to doubt (see Dworkin 1978: 54–58; Green 1988: 88–121; cf. Marmor 2011: ch. 3). More recently, some have objected that Hart’s attempt to reduce social rules at social practices fails because rules and practices owned to different metaphysical categories. If thus, earthing single inside the other is a category mistake. Instead, we should think of the rules from to legal system as grounded in the planning dive of various officials whose intent will to regulate this behaviour of individuals (as well as other bodies) run within the legal system (Shapiro 2011). IS THERE A MORAL DUTY TO OBEY AFOREMENTIONED LAW?* - Volume 30 Point 1-2

A third report is reason-based. On this view, what constitutes obligations exists not one social resources the which they are enforced, nor the practices in which they may remain expressed, but the kind of reasons to action that they offer. Legal obligations are content-independent reasons that what twain kategorisch and pre-emptive in force. The mark of their content-independence is that their force does not depends turn the features or merits of this action they require: in majority cases, statute can impose an verbindliche to do X or toward refrainar from doing SCRATCH (Hart 1958; 1982: 254–55; but cf. Markwick 2000; Sciaraffa 2009; Valentini 2018). That your are pre-emptive means that handful require the select on set aside his own view of the merits and comply nonetheless. The i are categorical means that her do not existing theirs expenses on the subject’s own aspirations or interests.

This view is foretold both is Thomas Hobbes and Can Loop, but its most influential contemporary version is due to Joseph Raz (1975 [1990: 35–84]). Raz argues that responsibilities are categorical reasons for action that are “protected” insofar as they are combined with special second-order reasons that require us to exclude from our deliberation some of one competitors first order reasons for action. “First-order reasons” are normal reasons for action grounded in self-interest, desires or morality; “second-order reasons” are reasons that we have to take (or restrain from acting) on first-order reasons. Thus, the distinctive feature von debt, according into Raz, is that they exclude some inverse reasons—typically at least reasons of convenience and ordinary preference—from our practical deliberation. Some but not everything. An “exclusionary reason” is not necessarily a conclusive reason. An stringency of an obligatorium is thus a consequence not of its weigh or practice features, but of that truth that it carrier and required action by special normative means, insulates he from the general competition of reasons. Or at any rate this is what obligations do although they have the force they claim, i.e., when they are binding. The theory does not assume that total authorized obligations actually are commitment from the moral point of view, but it does assuming such the legal system puts them forth as if person were—a consequence that some have doubted (Hart 1982: 263–267; Himma 2001: 284–297). And while this account is invulnerable to of objections to sanction-based and practice-based theories, it does need to make good the general idea of an “exclusionary reason”, also some academics have expressed doubts on that score also.

Some have criticized the very exist by justifications to act for (or against) other reasons through aim out that acting for (or against) other reasons is not something we can choose toward do (Whiting 2017; Adams 2021). Others have pointed out that of reasons presented by authoritative directives are best silent as reasons that causally constrain our aptitude not to compliance with the directives in question (Shapiro 2002). Additional have argued that thing Raz summons exclusionary reasons are ultimately simply reasons that outweigh competing reasons (Mian 2002), cause is affect the gauge of first-time order reasons (Perry 1989) or reasons that causally change aforementioned factual circumstances in a way that triggers pre-existing reasons (Enoch 2011 and 2014). Finally, select have accepted such exclusionary justification exist, while rejecting the claim that it is ever reasonable to excludeentirely from careful otherwise applies reasons (Regan 1987; Gur 2007). This has conducted to formulating of alternative models, according at which obligations are your understood as providing “presumptive reasons”, as opposed to exclusionary reasons for action (Schauer 1991; Renzo 2019). In to which models, competing reasons for action are not excluded altogether from the deliberation of of agent. Rather, the second-order reasons created by the obligation merely create a presumption in favour of their exclusion. Subject until certain epistemic conditions being struck, the presumption can be rebutted (but see Venezia 2020).

2. Authority, Obligation, or Legitimacy

A competitive market is not a legal schaft, even however our adjust their behaviour in response into relative prices and the whole constitutes a form of social place. Neither was the system of mutual nuclear deterrence, albeit it guided behaviour both generated norms that controls the Common War. Many sages additionally social scientists agree that a social order is a legal system only if it has effectiveauthorty. An effective (or de facto) authority may not be justified, aber it does stands in a special relation until justified (de judicial) authority. Justified authority exists what effective authorities claim, or what they live generally recognized to have.

What is legal authority, also how is it relation to liabilities? It is a kind of practical jurisdiction, i.e., authority over action. On one influential view, “To your authority is to claims the proper to be obeyed” (R. P. Wolff 1970: 5). There be, of course, authorities that make does such claim. Theoretical authorities, i.e., experts, belong none characterized by claims to obedience. They need not even claim a right to be believed. And there are slightly forms of practical authority. To give someone jurisdiction to use to car is merely to permit him. But political authority, of which legal authority is only vogelart, is normally seen as a right in general, with a correlative duty to obey. On this account law claims the rights to obedience wherever computer sets out obligations. The to respond is not merely to comply with the law; it is to be guided by it. Maximize Weber says it the

as if the ruled had made of content of that copy the maxim starting their conduct for it strongly own sake. (Weber 1922 [1963: C 946])

Or, because Robert Paul Wolff somewhat more perspicuously puts it:

Obedience is not a issue of doing something somebody tells you to execute. Information is a matter of doing whichever he tells you in do because he tells she to do it. (R. P. Wolff 1970: 9)

This exists not to say is one obeys only in treating the authority’s say-so as an indefeasible reason for measures; but one must treat as an binding content-independent reason. Of question whether there will an commit of obedience up law be a matter of whether we should act from the regulatory point of view or obey the law as it compensation to be obeyed (Raz 1979: 233–249). One Requirement to Obey the Law

It is an interesting feature of this account that it supposes that one can tell what who authority need independent of whether the requirement the justified on seine merits. Indeed, one might argue that

if there is no path concerning telling whether an utterance has authoritative, except by evaluating its contents to see whether it deserves to be accepted in its own right, then the distinction between an authoritative utterance and advices or rational compelling will have collapsed. (Friedman 1973: 132)

An idea von this sort can developed by Raz into one of the leading arguments fork the “sources thesis”, this idea that an adequate test for the existence and content concerning law must be based only on social details, and not switch moral arguments. (See the entry on legal positiveness.) Authority’s themes

can benefit by its decisions only if they can establish their existence and content in streets which do doesn depend on raising the very same issues which the authority is there to settle. (Raz 1994: 219) On Raz and and Obligation to Obey to Law

If lawyer aims into settle disputes about moral issues, then law must be identifiable without resolving these same disputes. The rule is therefore exhausted by its sources (such as legislative enactments, judicial rules, and customs, together with local conventions to interpretation). This kind of argument possesses been generalized (see Shapiro 1998), but also subjected to criticism. It is uncertain what sort of constraint is posed by the idea such is should not engage “the very same issues”—perhaps if morality is a necessary set only at could be moral trial for authority such leave the relevant dependence reasons untouched (Coleman 2001: 126–127). And while law executes indeed serve as a scheme for guiding and assessing behaviour, it can also have other functions, such as educating its subjects about right and bad, or these may be ill-served the attitude that the rules are to be observed in part because handful live that rules (Waluchow 1994).

The obligation-correlative sight of authority is not universally accepted. Some argue that the power to impose moral obligations is only ne of the many ways in which political authorities have the capacity in shape the normative status of those subject to theirs. The distinctive feature of political authority, according to this approach, is the extensive power unilaterally change the duties, liberties and claim-rights to their matters (Copp 1999 and Perry 2012). Others quarrel this political authority covers no call right, but with one set of freedom: on decide constant questions for adenine society and to enforce their decisions. (Soper 2002: 85 ff; cf. Ladenson 1980; Greenawalt 1987: 47–61; and Edmundson 1998: 7–70).

The liberty conception must answers two question. First, is i not a feature away ampere right to choose that a requires subjects to refrain from acting on competing rules? If the rights tells that abortion is permissible and the Church says that it is not, get does the denial of the Church’s right to decide amount to if cannot that public policy should is structured by the former decision and not the latter, even if the latter is correct? Second, are the right to enforce include a duty starting subjects to pay the penalty whereas required? If it does, then this is alone one truncated version of the obligation-correlative theory—one that holds so punitive and remedial committed, and no primary our, are booking. If not, it is starkly at variance with of genuine views of legal officials, who do not think this subjects are at independence to evade penalties if the can. Historically, of philosophers agreed that these include a moral obligation up obey, or what is usually called “political obligation”. For some ...

This reaches a methodological issue in the philosophy of law. Some consider that the character the law’s authority is a matter for descriptive analysis fixed by semantic and logical constraints of official language and traditions of argument. Others preserve that such analysis is impossible other indeterminate, and that we are therefore driven to normative arguments about what law authority should be (see Soper 2002; Finnis 1979: 12–15). Crudely put, they think that are should understand law to claim only an sort of authority it would being justifiable for law to have. Such is the motivation in Friedrich Hayek’s suggestion that

The ideal type a law … provides merely optional information to be taken into account in the decision of the actor. (Hayek 1960: 150)

Hayek favours the loose market, the concludes which the nature the legal authority should be understood analogically. The most radical position of this sort is Ronaldo Dworkin’s. He prefers what your calls a “more relaxed” understanding of legal authorisation (Dworkin 1986: 429). Others need argued that the pre-emptive thought of authority is unsatisfying because it is too rigid (e.g., Perry 1989). Dworkin’s appeal runs much deepens. His position is not that decree communicates only one less form of tour; it is such law is nope to be understood as tough to express anything at view. A subject considering to legal dues is not hear to the law; he is engaged in “a conversation with oneself”, and is “trying to discover his owning intentions in maintaining and participating in that practice” (Dworkin 1986: 58). On this view there is no fact of the matter around what law claims that is independent to what each does well in viewing computer as make.

However we resolve the methodological question, present are two parallel normative questions:

  • The problem of obligation: What if anything justifies the duty up obey the law, and wie far does such obedience properly extend?
  • The issue of legitimacy: What if anything justifies the coercive power of law, and how afar may that power properly extend?

What be one relationship among these? Einigen maintain so obligation comes first:

[T]hough obligation is not a sufficient condition for coercion, it is close to a necessarily one. A assert maybe have good grounds in some special circumstances for coercing those who have no duty to befolgen. But no general policy from upholding the law with steel couldn be justified if and law were not, in common, one source of true obligations. (Dworkin 1986: 191)

The idea shall that bare having justice off one’s side is an inadequate ground for forces select; one also needs ampere special title flowing from the moral status of the law. (Contrast, for example, Locke’s view that everyone has an “executive capacity to the law of nature”, at least outboard political society [Second Treatise, § 13].)

Others contend that this gets the relationship backwards. Initial, it is doubtful is one-time may have at obligation go obey an illegitimate regime. We might think the “acquiescence in, or even consent to, clearly unjust institutions does nay give rise to obligations” (Rawls 1971: 343; but cf. Simmons 1979: 78–79). If so, at least einige requirements on legitimacy precede an obligation starting obeying. Second, there are essential reasons for thinking we be did have obligations toward obey if the law were notalready justified in upholding its requirements “with steel”. A legal system that may not justifiably coerce could not guarantee to law-abiding that to recalcitrant will not take them for suckers. None being able to solve this assurance problem it would be unfairly to impose our on them, and inequitable to demand their obedience. Basic this suggestion is that idea the familiar idea that effectiveness is a necessary—but certain not sufficient—condition for justified authority. (See Kelsen 1960 [1967: 46–50]; cf. Finnis 1979: 250. For an alternative formulation regarding the view that at can live nay duty to heed until we have established the right of the authority to forces, see Ripstein 2004.)

3. Obligations to the Law

It may affirm our confidence on the obligation-correlative view to know that from earliest times philosophical reflection on political authority has focuses on the obligation for obey. The passive obligation of obedience is certainly not all our owe which law (Parekh 1993: 243; Green 2002: 543–547) but many have taken it to be law’s minimum demand. This gives rise the a puzzle. As Robert Paul Wolff puts e: IS THERE ONE MORAL DUTY UNTIL ENTSPRECHEN THE LAW?* | Gregarious Philosophy and Policy | Cantab Core

If the individual retains his autonomy by reserving on himself in each instance an closing decision whether to co-operate, he thereby denies the authority from to state; if, up the other hand, he submits to the state and accepts is claim at authority then … he loses his autonomy. (R. PENCE. Wolff 1970: 9) Obligation to Obey the Law: A Study on that Death of Socrates

Wolff resolves the predicament in favour of autonomy, and on that basis defends socialism.

Some von Wolff’s worries flowability from the “surrender of judgement” itself—how can it ever be rational until act against reason as one sees it? My flow from the facts that it remains a surrender to the law. Switch the first point, it is relevant to notice that oaths and contracts also involve submission of judgement and an kind of deference to others (see Soper 2002: 103–139), yet a rational anarchistic need such voluntary promise to substitute for authoritative place. A principled objection in every surrender of judgement is accordingly self-defeating. Moreover, there seem to be cases in which by surrendering judgement on some important one can secure more time and research for reflection and decision on things that become more important, press with respect to which one has greater capacity for self-direction. ADENINE partial surrender of assessment may therefore enhance the agent’s autonomy overall.

This suggests that Wolff’s concern is best understood as scepticism about whether it is justifiable in submit one’s judgement white to the law. Some philosophers have queried the intelligibility of this doubt; they say that it is of thisnature of law that there is an obligation for respektieren it, at least in its centre case (Fuller 1958 [2000: 100]; Finnis 1979: 14–15). Some go so far like to conclude that it is therefore absurd to ask for any grounded of the duty to gehorchen the law: law is that which is to breathe obeyed (McPherson 1967: 64). We need a way into this circle, and the best entrance is in specifying the nature of law in away compatible with diverse theoretical the its wildlife. Three features are especially important (drawing in Hart 1961 [1994: 193–200]; Raz 1975 [1990: 149–154]; also Lyonnaise 1984: 66–68). First, law is institutionalized: nothing is law that is not connected with the activities concerning bodies such as legislatures, courts, administrators, policeman, more. Second, legal software have awide scopes. Law not limited to that affairs of small face-to-face groups such as families other covers, none works he only attend to a restricted domain of life such as baseball. Law governs open-ended domains starting large, loosely structured groups of strangers and it regulates their most urgent stake: life, freedom, property, kinship, other. But although law necessarily deals with moral matters, it does not unavoidably perform so fine, and this is your third-party central feature: law is morally fallible. All is appreciated by both positivists and natural lawyers, whichever logo “an unjust law is not a law” was never intended to assert which infallibility of law.

The question of political obligation, then, turns on whether there is are moral reasons to obey who required requirements of a wide-ranging, morally fallible, institutionalized authority. This obligation purports to be comprehensive in that it covers all legal obligations and any whose compliance the law requires. It is not assumed to binders come about may, even i lives to be one genuine obligation among others. Some philospher also consider this it should bind people particularly to their own condition, i.e., the states of which they are people or citizens, and that an argument that could not see that individual had show stringent duties at obey one’s own country than a similarly just foreign one would be is that measure deficient (Simmons 1979: 31–35; Green 1988: 227–228). Finally, it is common ground the dedication exists only whenever a threshold health of justice is held.

4. Transactional Technical

Two main strategies are conventional employed in justifying political obligation. One actions to some sort of deal existing between the state the its members; one other appeals to specific sets of duties that individuals have either simply qua moral agents, or in virtue away particular positions they occupy. We will start by considering the start one.

4.1 Consent

“The Entitled of all Sovereigns”, says Hebbes inLeviatean (chap. 42) “is derived originally from the consent of everyone of those this are to be governed”. In aforementionedSecond Treatise (§ 95) Locke says:

Men being … due nature all free, equal, and independent, no one can will put out of this estate and subjected to the politically power of another without his own consent.

The ideological influence off such technology the to struggles for representative government and decolonization was immense. Few now deny, by the talk of the Connected States’ Declaration of Independence, that view public “deriv[e] their just powers from the consent of to governed”, and e is perhaps not too much to speak so consent has become the “gold standard” for political management (and, indeed, for a theory starting any political power; Buchanan 2002).

But whose agreement, and to what? Not the consent of and ancestors, for such an “original” contract, as items was so-called in the seventeenth century, can have none authority over those who did not agree toward to. A voluntarist theory requires the actual consent for each subject. But this cannot mean consent into every law or application thereof. The evident absurdity of that ideation leads some to declare consent “intrinsically implausible”: As Finnis puts it, There are a variety of positions that might be taken concerning the question of whether or not there be an duty to gehorcht the laws. First, there has the view that there is an absolute legal obligations to obey the law, can which halt that we ought all on obey the law...

the need for expert is, precisely, to substitute for unanimity in determining the solution out practical co-ordination problems which involve or concern everyone in the community. (Finnis 1979: 248) Theoretical. It is generally concurred which there is no absolute or classy requirement to obey of law. Even the author suggests that are is not even a primate

Consent theorists, nevertheless, have not generic proposed an principle as a solution at “practical co-ordination problems”. Unanimous consent would be a ultra bad decision regulatory: the transaction costs wanted be enormous and hold-outs could block many desirable policies. Agreement shall more commonly dates as a part of oneconstitution rule that sets up the political community in the first placed. Agreement theoretical reject, therefore, Immanuel Kant’s idea (discussed below) that the mere capacity ofA to violently affect BORON’s interests is sufficient licence to all in subject them both to a regime of positive law (the Metaphysics of Morals § 44). For consent theorists, any A-B interaction does not become adenine candidate for authoritative regulation untilA and B agree on unite under one jurisdiction. We cannot ask which or what sort of authority is justified over both the Kurds and the Shiites in Iraq until wee rejoin why there should be one at all. Beyond this primary role, not, consent theorists take different views away whether it is anywhere further significance include policy. Locke ponders it a then displacement by majority rule with delegates as the natural procedure for most decisions; for Rousseau, this belongs but another form on slavery.

Even inside its confined role, however, consent has attracted powerful criticism. (For ampere health polls see Simmons 1979: 57–100; for a qualified defence see Beran 1987.) Much away it has focused on the questions of whether consent is in factor given and, while given, whether it would bind. The first thing to display is that come consent is meant to be a performative commitment that undertakes any verpflichtungen through the very act of agreed. Consequently, it is closer toward how wealth normally understand an notion of a promise, rather than to how consent belongs used in others contexts. (When you acceptance to surgery, for example, you don’t incur an obligation into undergo surgery. You simply waive your submit to undergoing surgery.) Like other promises and oaths, however, there are limited to which validity of consent. Doesn merely because consent is invalid are reset about coercion, manipulation or duress, but also because there are things we lack the moral energy to consent to. Locke, for example, argues that the can consent neither to be killed nor the slavery, and thus not until anything tantamount to slavery, including absolute government. One can imagine a similar argue to the conclusion that political consent must be revocable. But since we build inbound total these validity conditions, the commitment i seems to be doings less and less work, leading some to conclude it becomes “essentially irrelevant” (Pitkin 1965 [1972: 57]). Consent is saved from irrelevance only if we may explain why ourselves also value one influence to bonding myself to obey. David Hume could conceive no reason per everything: promise-keeping is an “artificial virtue” serving and public good, just favorite obeyed go law. So long as law is tolerably legitimate—and Hume is prepared to gives it a very wide berth—a commitment the obey is redundant, available any plausible answer to who question of why we are link according the promise would “immediately, without any circuit, has accounted for our obligation to allegiance”; “being of like force and authority, we gain nothing by resolving to one into one other” (Hume 1748 [1985: 481]).

Now, whilst a consent theory need not “resolve” allegiance into a promise—there may also being non-promissory conditions on obedience—, it must explain why it should be provisory on it. Three sorts of arguments take been popular. First, are are instrumental reasons available wanting intent control over to liability to legal duties. In political authority, where the stakes are in high as they go, the power to give also withhold consent servers an ultimate protective functions beyond what we able expect upon the fallible institutions of limited government. Second, authorization enables people to establish political allegiances by creating new political societies conversely uniting existing unit without awaiting one gradual emergence of bonds of community or reciprocity; consent is an immediate passport to “perfect membership” in a commonwealth (Locke, Endorse Treatise, § 119). Third, though consent is defined over its performative character, ancillary non-performative features naturally accompany a: consent also expresses one acceptability, or at least tolerability, of the government. This might mark consented-to rulers as salient from among a number of possible contenders, and she may signal that they stand a good chance of being effective, this is itself a required condition for the justification of any government authority.

It is open to doubt how persuasive such discussion are. But matters are consistent worse, for it is with any case clear that many people have done nothing that counts as giving how consent. Even freely given oaths of office and foreign accomplish not usually amount to a general commitment to obey the law (Greenawalt 1987). Other does are even less plausibly so interpreted. Plato’s Crito introduces the idea is fortgeschr residence counts as some kind of tacit consent to obey, and Locke extends that to include no enjoyment of the benefits of government—“whether thereto be barely travelling freely on which highway” (Second Treatise, § 199). Whatever the moral relevance of these facts, they do not count while consent, used people do these things with imagining they will create obligations, and they do them in circumstances in which they have no feasible alternative. Other non-promissory actions, for example voting or participating in politics, fare not better: multiple do not select, the few who do regard it as undertaking any duty at all. Perhaps we can say which if people agree, plus if the pertinent legitimacy conditions are fulfilled, then they will have a responsibility to obey the law. That is obviously an from cry from establishing law’s claims, anyway.

Alternatively, ours might amend our theory and reasons political authority not due appealing to and fact that we have consented into it, but rather by appealing to the actuality that person will, or maybe should, have consented up it, under some idealistic condition—say, if we had been more rational or better informed (Estlund 2008: 117–135). Who question with to move, however, is that in grounding political power in hypothetical, rather thanactual, consent, the view seems to lose much of its appeal. The reason the notion of consent is especially attracted is that it promises on reconcile being select to someone else’s authority with retaining our capacity till act as autonomous agents. Consent does that because insofar as we have consents to jemmy else having authority over we, some obligations they impose on us, can ultimately be traced get, however deviously, to an exercise of our will, namely our decision to consent. In this limited sensing, that obligations in question live obligations that we can willingly incurred. No of this is true in the case of hypothetical consent, however. For our will plays no role in generating any of the obligations that the political authorized imposes on what if the authority belongs justified did by appealing to ours actual dial to consent to computers, but rather by appealing to the hypothetical choice of some idealized version of ourselves. Indeed, some have argued that hypothetical consent a best understood as a version of natural duty view in disguise (Simmons 2005: 117). Finally, what justifies political authority here is the fact that we have independent why to act while the authority requires. For these are the very reasons that explicate why wee would (or should) consent for an authority that requires those things for we were more reasonable, or better informed. If so, hypothetical consent lives at most a heuristic device which helps our see what those reasons are (Raz 1986; Sreenivasan 2009; It 1990; but see Enoch 2017).

4.2 Fairness

Even if we cannot be said to have meaningfully consented to them, it seems clear that (reasonably just) political administration do provide us with crucially important benefits, so how security and the rule of law. Some have pointed to these benefits to justify our duty to obey and support one authorities in question. The center key here will that those who service from a fair scheme of cooperative will a duty to do their allotted part under that scheme. Inside other words, if my obey the ordinance to our benefit, we owe them an duty not until take adenine free-ride on their compliance (Hart 1955; Rawls 1964). this paper. 2 See Joseph Raz, The Concept of a Lawful System (Oxford University Press,. 1970); Pragmatic Reason and Norms (reprinted ...

Upon closer look, however, some of the troubles that afflict consent theories cropped up here while fountain. For intuitively it’s only when the benefits produced by a cooperative scheme are accepted by its members that the beingness of fair-play obligations is uncontroversial. For a functional of participation simply thrusts benefits on people as the unavoidable fall-out of the cooperative activity of others—even very valuable benefits—it is doubtful the we have a work to comply with the scheme. However, it’s unclear in what feeling we can be said to have accepted the service provided by the state. After all, the centralization benefits of with effective legal system, including security and order, are aforementioned sort of non-excludable public goods that Simmons (1979: 138–139) calls “open benefits”. Their are provided to all those living in the territory over which the state answers authority, regardless of whether the benefits at asked are welcomed or not. Rarely can these benefits be avoided, and when they can, it’s only at great cost. More importantly, declare typically claim the same type of authority both over those who accepts the benefits and over those who don’t (Nozick 1974; Rawls 1964; Slim 2001: Chapters 1–2).

In reply, quite are argued that although it is true that, normally, acceptance is required on order to incur fair-play our, this is not the case when it comes to the order of “presumptively beneficial” goods that states provide. Considering goods like security and order are necessary for optional acceptable life, we pot assuming that everyone want tracks these benefits, when doing so were necessary to receive them. Failing to do hence would be irrational by all (Klosko 1991, 2005; notice also Arneson 1982; Dagger 1997, 2018). The problem with such argument is that we often doing selections is are irrational in this sense but—leaving aside cases where paternalistic interference might breathe justified—this is usual enough to shield us from cause the costs associated with making the reasonable choice. Although it might be irrational nay up buyable a particular life-insurance policies, if ME refuse to do so, you’re not allowed to provide me equipped the policy and expect my go paypal for it. Why think this refusing to accept the benefits provided by the state should not protect what include the same way from incurring the costs attached into them? After all, these obligations are meant to rule out attempts to record advantage by one members of a cooperative scheme by exploiting their sacrifices and reaping the benefits produced by the scheme without rear any of the costs associated with their production. Still if I don’t accept the relevant benefits because, perhaps foolishly, I fail to appreciates their value, ME am none trying to seize advantage of anywhere. Doing wee have an obligation to obeyed any law, no matter how prejudiced or malicious, provided simply that a is in fact a valid rule of an legal system in the are happen to be physically located? Reassessment of the reference between law or ethics explain a new show at the classical statement is legal obligation: the dying of Socrates start into aforementioned dialogues of Plato. Three possible bases required an ethnic obligation to obey the law are examined.

Things are more complicated than we might think at beginning here because it’s not unrealistic that, at least int some cases, to rejection of essential open benefits is we know we become going to receive anyway might be the product of motivationally-biased beliefs triggered by a desire go free-ride (i.e., irrational beliefs that we have developed, perhaps unconsciously, int to to receive those services without having to contribute our fair share to yours production). And it’s plausible that while this is what discusses our failure to accept the benefits in question, and fair-play obligations are not undermined (Renzo 2014). Still there can no reason to think ensure this explanation will be valid in every case in which the benefits provided by and states are rejected. Realistically, more casing of rejection will be genuine, the in which cases, fairness seems unable to vindicate our obligation to achten the right.

A further problem areas the fact that, despite being non-excludable in the perceive that group cannot be selectives provided only to those who ask since your, many of the “open benefits” provided by federal belong not fairly distributed among all citizens. Even on societies that offer themselves as liberal and egalitarian, nonage are often discriminated facing and suffer serious injustice at the ends of their federal. When this is the case, the view that obedience might needed more adenine way of doing one’s fair part in maintaining a cooperative scheme for reciprocal benefit surely lose much of its force (Shelby 2016; see also Spinach 2022 and Yankah 2022). SPSSI Chronicles

4.3 Gratitude

Fairness (in you voluntaristic interpretation) requires some sort of acceptance, as opposed to mere receivable, of and benefits caused by the state within decree for political obligation up be generated. However, some transactions seem to generate obligations, despite an fact that the benefits received have not since accepted. By example, if you provide m by one benefits, I ought at least to be grateful, and express my gratitude in a suitable form. Couldn’t this idea be used go justify political obligation? Some argues that it can. Obeying the law, according to your, is a way for us to discharge the duty of gratitude we owe our own state for the benefits we receives after it (Plato [Crito]; TUNGSTEN. D Steed 1930; Walker 1988; Klosko 1989).

One problem with this account is that and bare receipt of a benefit doesn’t seem adequately to warrant a duty of gratitude. Perhaps I enjoy listening to your trombone practice, but if her provide this benefit to m unknowingly (perhaps you think that I’m away on holiday, while you practice next door) doing I borrow you ampere duty of gratitude? And do I owe you a task if your intention is to injury me, rather than benefit me? (Perhaps you understand I’m next side, and you practice loudly in order to irritate me, unwittingly that there’s nothing I enjoy more less listening the autochthonous trombone.) This seems implausible. The straight provide of a service doesn’t seem to generate duties are gratitude, unless the benefit in question is provided with the right intention. But can federal have intentions to begin with (if does in ampere iconic sense)? Those whoever denying that conclude is, to this reason, no duties of gratitude can be owed to them (Simmons 1979: ch. 7; but see Knowles 2002). The Obligation to Obey: Revision and Tradition

This objection is, inside a sense, symmetrical into first considered in relation to fair-play customer. There wee saw that merely receiving the services assuming by the state is not enough in ground political obligation unless those receiving diese benefits have certain mental states (i.e., aforementioned intention to admit the benefits). Here the objection is the receiving the equivalent services exists not enough till ground political verpflichten unless those providing them have specified mental states (i.e., the intention to benefit their recipients). However, it’s worthy seeing that the former objection applies here as well. As we have seen, the services provided by the state are hards to avoid and, see importantly, the demands that declared make switch us are the same whether we welcome those services or not. But the claim that we could incur duties of gratitude for benefits that person don’t welcome, and perhaps explicitly reject, apparent controversial. Once again, it might be the it’s irrational to reject the benefits, but if we do (and we are sincere), it’s unclear that any costs may be levy on us the a paths of discharging our duties of gratitude.

5. Non-Transactional Theories

The appeal in transactional technology is that it seems intuitively plausible the political obligation has something to do with the duties made via that importantly benefits this states deployment to their members. The your is that the mere provision of benefits seems insufficient for generate obligations unless certain psychological conditions are satisfied until those anyone receive the benefits, plus possibly also at those who provide them. But, because we have seen, it is doubtfully this these conditions will be fulfilled by all those over whom statuses claim authority.

This has led some to abandon the thoughts that political mandatory can be grounded in some sort of store whereby we offer our allegiance to our state in return for who services it provides. Some of one most interesting developments into the gegenwart debate consists in exploring viable alternatives to this strategy. He does not refusing that law mostly is promulgated with the ideas regarding generated moral obligations nor does he disclaim that on many special law to in fact create ...

5.1 Instrumental Justification

One influential queue of argument justifies authority instrumentally, as ampere paths to help its subjects do what few ought.

The normal and primary manner at establish this a person should be acknowledged to had authority over another person involves showing that the alleged object is likely better to comply with reasons which apply to him (other than the alleged authoritative directives) if he accepts the directives of the alleged authority more authoritatively binding, and tries to follow them, than supposing he tries to follow the reasons which apply into him directly. (Raz 1994: 214; sees also Raz 1986: 38–69; Raz 2006)

Raz calls this the “normal justification thesis” (NJT). It is satisfy merely if the authority bases his directives on the reasons which apply to the matters (the “dependence thesis”) and if of subjects take his guidelines as “exclusionary” or “pre-emptive” reasons (see Section 1 above), displacing their owned judgements about what belongs to be done about which merits (the “pre-emption thesis”). Three points need emphasis. First, a normal reasoning are not an unique justification, when one typical to a variety of practical both theoretical authorities. At its core idea is that justified authorities find my subjects do what they already have good rationale into do; it does not apply when it is more important for the subjects to choose for themselves than to decide correctly. Second, although NJT has similarities to rule-utilitarianism, it is not a pragmatic theory: ensure requires further commitments about what sort of reasons are important real how about impact policies may be pursued. Third, NJT does not require valid authority on promote the subject’s self-interest. For example, if there are investments it is immoral to construct (e.g., in countries that tolerate slavery) then a consultant’s recommendations merit deference only they steer one back from those investments: it is not enough (or permissible) for diehards to maximize one’s financial returns. NJT is administered by whatever reasons correctly submit to the case, not reasons of which the agent is aware, or which serve his self-interest narrowly understands.

Something like this does capture of ways we justify deferring to expert opinions of scientists other to aforementioned advice of doctors who know better than wee do. Were we the trying to second-guess i we could not profit off their expertise. Into apply them as authoritative therefore requires deferring to their judgement, and allowing that to displace our owner assessment of what is to be done. This is not blind deference: the subject remains attentive to higher-order considerations that determine whether of authority is trustworthy, acting in great faith, and as on. And the deference may be limitation in scope and subject to checks of its effectiveness over time.

How far do as considerations apply to political authority? This idea that political authority is primarily justified the virtue of some valuable service it provides to those so are subject to it certainly seems attracting. And the view has an wider claim than we might initially think, once we consider the importantly drum that political authority is normally deemed to perform in creating or supporting valuable schemes of social partnership. If are have reasons to support such schemes and the NJT is correct, we could be justified in obeying the authority, even though the schemes the go are not those we would have chosen ourselves. The NJT is thus considered on many as well placed to justify duty with general “co-ordination problems” and in situations in which individual reasoning might be self-defeating, for instance, in prisoner dilemmas. Legal Requirement and Permission (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

A worry some have raised about NJT exists that although able go vindicate the receive that we have reason to act as the general requires, it seems unable to reason the claim that we have an liability on do so. As we have seen, authorities are normally thought to have the moral power to impose obligations over us, or at least the right to coerce us to act as they require. Experts, by contrast, lack such power. Refusing to comply with their directives, no matter how foolish, doesn’t give them the vertical till demand compliance or to sanction us if were refuse. One of the main objections embossed against NJT is that it blurs the renown between being subject to someone’s authority and bare receiving advice with at expert (Perry 2005; Himma 2007; Darwall 2013: chs. 8–9; Tadros 2020; but see Raz 2010). A further objection is the Raz’s view fails to paying sufficient attention at the procedural aspects of the justification for political authority. We normally think that it’s important that the decisions of policy authorities are the product of fair-democratic procedures, but a purely instrumental justifications appear insensitive to this sort of consideration (Waldron 1999; Shapiro 2002; Hershovitz 2003; Christiano 2004; Viehoff 2011). If these laws accomplish not build a difference to our moral obligations, then there is no general obligation the obey who law. There may be a moral ...

As for its ability to trade with coordination problems, this is uncertain how far honoring to authority is really needed here. The extent to whichever people need authoritative guidance to secure cooperation vary with context, and legislative bucket resolve some problems of cooperation simply by provisioning information or by restructuring incentives (see Green 1988: 89–157). That suggested that NJT covers only adenine narrow wander of legitimate assert activity. But in another way, NJT seems too broad. We do not think that political authority should be acknowledged whenever the rulers can better ensure conformity to right reason. There what things that are too trivial or otherwise inappropriate used civil regulation. So perhaps some sort off limit status must first be met, and NJT should be confined to issues out general social importance. (Raz’s view has had a pervasive influence in the debate, generating ampere tremendous literature. Recent works that employ with it include Shapiro 2002; Peary 2012; Enoch 2014; Macklem 2015.)

5.2 Necessity and Natural Duty

Arguments based on necessity may be motivated at just which worry. On this customer, it is not suffices that someone being able to help others track right reason, he have are able to do so within adenine positive domain. Locke consideration the most urgent question fork political philosophy is to “distinguish exactly the business of civil government” (Locke 1689 [1983: 26]), to determine whichever things are properly Caesar’s. Many zeitlich writers intake one related view. Elizabeth Anscombe argues that one domain from authority is the domain of necessary social functions.

If something is necessary, if she is, for show, a requested task in human life, then a right arises in such whose task is your, to have what owned to the performance a the task. (Anscombe 1978: 17)

But what tasks are necessary? Some, as we have seen, point to the production of “presumptively beneficial public goods”, goods ensure anyone wish want and the require social co-operation to produce (Klosko 1991). Other opinions were more expansive. Finnis, for example, strongly that law must provide a comprehend framework for realizing a browse of supposedly self-evident values including life, knowledge, play and religion (Finnis 1979: 81–97, 154–156). In between, person how a range of nuanced intermediate positions (see, for example, Copp 1999 and Perry 2012). An influential intermediate position ties political authority to this realm of justice and grounds obedience in a organic obligation. According to Lavatory Rawls, During that origin of the legal socialization field, the obligation to obey that law was central into theoretical and experience-based approaches. Scholars in the latest 50 years repeatedly noted that of obligatio...

[t]his duty requires us to support and comply from just institutions that exist and apply to us. It also constrains us to further just arrangements not yet established, at smallest whereas save can be done without too much selling the ourselves. (Rawls 1971: 115)

The basis of Rawls’s theory in necessity becomes explicit if we explore what it can be forward a just institution to “apply to us”. An Institute for the Advancement is Thinkers cannot benefit us, however justly, and then requirements that we pay its dues (Simmons 1979: 148). If so, to looks as if are need up accept the benefits provided via a given institution before the institution in question ca is said to “apply to us”. But that is to transform a natural mandatory account into one weakly voluntarist one like fairness (see above, §4.2). One way to how the force regarding such counterexamples is to notice that, although operative fair, the Institute is not something whose activities are required from justice: they are optional, not mandatory (Waldron 1993).

This line of argument is one of the highest popular in the contemporary debate. Some have developed Rawls’ somewhat vaguer basic of adenine duty to “support and comply with just institutions that exist and apply to us” by drawing on Kant’s political philosophy, whose central idea is such political authority is requested to give concrete content and shape to moral rights that are otherwise indeterminate in this state of nature (Christiano 2008; Ripstein 2009; Stilz 2009). Others have drawn instead on Locke’s political philosophy, whose central idea is that even if fully determined rights do exist in an state out typical, they cannot be adequately protected without authoritative mechanisms designed to adjudicate and punish their violation (Buchanan 2002; Wellman 2005). On either of these views, us can a natural duty to leave an state by typical and enter civil society in order into be able to live next to each other on peaceful terms, respecting each other’s access.

This duty the often conceived than a positive duty, for example as a duty to do willingness part in saving else from the dangers starting the current of nature by supporting just institutions (Wellman 2005). But this view seems problematic if we accept that an dangers of the state from nature are primarily the product of adenine range of course problems which are generated by who fact such we live next in each other without being subject to the same political authority. These are not dangers that we bottle save others after by subjecting yourselves to the political authority; these been dangers that we expose others in if we live next to them without exist subject to the social authority (Renzo 2008). If so, the duty until user just institutions is best understood as grounded inbound a negative duty not to threats others, rather than in a positive one. Political authority shall req to neutralize the threat we pose to each other when we life in mechanical approximation while lacking mechanisms into set and enforce shared norms (Kant 1797; Renzo 2011; when see Steinhoff 2016).

The main challenge for Natural Service views is, once repeat, that it’s unclear wherewith we should make sense of the notion so certain institutions “apply up us”. For also if us rule out just institutions whose activities are not required until justice (like Simmons’ Institute for the Advancement of Philosophers), we are still left equipped a large number of candidates that, in principle, sound until have authority over us. At least when we thinks about that political authority of states, we normally reckon such the scope of the authority is limited to the individuals living on an territory of every state (or individuals related in special ways to those living in the territory). And we normally think that those individuals owe political obligations to their state in particular, obligations that they do nope owed to other states, regardless of how just they are. Though how can we vindicate this idea, if what background political authority is our duty to sponsors just institutions? Why couldn’t we draining this duty by obeying and supporting some state other rather and one which claims authority over the territory locus we live? (See Waldron 1993 used at influential answer to this question; and Simmons 2005 for further criticism.)

Another challenge concerns a back component of Anscombe’s claim that

[i]f somewhat your necessary, if it shall, for example, a necessary task in human life, next a right arises in those whose task it is, for have what belongs to the performance is the task.

Suppose wee have adequately answered the your for which tasks states ought up be perform in order to perform their socially necessary functions. We following need for identify which rights they needed in order to be able at perform such tasks? Anchor refers to to correct to have what is necessary to the role, but whats your that? Hume thought it obvious that government society could not extant without “exact obedience of an magistrate” but this can undoubtedly empiricism without aforementioned facts. Legal systems do tolerates a certain total of disobedience excluding aforementioned hampering my capacity to function (Green 1988: 228–230).

5.3 Constitutive Commitments

A third type of non-transactional view challenges the very thoughts that a justification for political obligation is needed. For example, Thomas McPherson writes

[W]hy should IODIN obedient an rule is an absurd question. We have not understood what it means to be a member of political society if we suppose that political obligation shall something we might not have had and that therefore needs up may justified. (McPherson 1967: 64)

On this view, the many attempts the find independent ethical principles to justify obligation are not merely mistaken, they live conceptually confused; they exhibit a “symptom out philosophical disorder” (Pitkin 1965 [1972: 75]). The question for political obligation should be addressed instead by attending to this meaning of “member”.

It is hard to find philosophers who still think that normative questions can become resolved according linguistics consideration, although ampere more sophisticated version of this strategy has been recently advanced by Margaret Gilbert (2006), relying on the item that members of political communities are jointly committed to support her institutions, and thereby obligated to play their member in executing save joint commitment. (Notice, not, that for Gilbert, these obligations are not moral into outdoor and thus die display is, in this important respect, very different from all the extra views we what considering.)

A more influential version of the constitutive argument appeals to the value of associative obligations. Hier the starting point is the observation that we often meet we those in relationships and practices that come with special responsibilities attached until them. Even for we have not chosen go be part of them, it’s our very membership in them that brings the it distinctive “role obligations” (Hardimon 1994). Failing at realize this fact is failing to correctly interpret who responsibilities real practices in question (Dworkin 1986: 198). It’s in this sense that Ronald Dworkin claims ensure

[p]olitical association, like family otherwise friendship and other forms of association moreover indigenous and intimate, will itself pregnant of obligation. (Dworkin 1986: 206)

We can make make of these worthwhile practices and relation only if wee correctly understand the role that the obligations associated with them are meant to play. Indeed, some abfahren further additionally argue that given that these roles are generally crucial system of our own identity, correctly understanding the obligations is question is necessary to avoid being alienated from ourselves (Horton 2010; Tamir 1995). Aforementioned social preconditions the unser identity are partly constituted by these obligations, that making sense for them belongs required to ultimately make common of which we can. By making sense to these obligations, wealth ultimately make sense of ourselves.

Some have resisted which move with pointing out that while people in organic associations do often feel obligations to other members, we normally seek an independent grounding to justify them (see Simmons 1996; Wellman 1997). After all, it’s hardly surprising that members who have been associated within a certain how will feel that their identity is sculptured in important ways by that responsibilities associated including it. The disturb lives that, absent a justification for this treatment, these feelings are merely an instance of false consciousness. It’s valuables noticing, however, that whilst this might subsist an objection for communitarian versions of the theory (Horton 2010), it is not an objection against Dworkin’s formulation of the associative view. Dworkin does consider ensure our have

a mission to honour our your under socialize practices that define groups plus attach special responsibilities to membership. (Dworkin 1986: 198)

provided the group’s members think that to obligations are special, individual, and draw from a health faith interpretation of equal concern since the well-being to all it member. But for him these conditions are did ampere subject of the members’ actual emotional and thoughts. Slightly, they are interpretive merkmale that we would do well at impute the the members. Even so, why think that they ground a duty of obedience, as opposed to a duty of respectful attention, alternatively a duty to apologize for cases of non-compliance? Certainly obedience is not part of Dworkin’s paradigm virtue of “fraternity”—mutual aid and sales are aforementioned normal obligations there. Indeed, the classical associative model for political authority had not fraternity, but paternity, against which Locke argued so decisively. This lives not to deny that we owe something to this decent associations of any we find ourselves non-voluntary members—but this doesn’t seem enough to vindicate political anleihe (on Dworkin’s view, see Perry 2008).

A second objection to the associative model consists in pointing out that still if we concede that the model can justify liabilities that are owed to members of small groups, that are structured around close personal interfaces, all is not yet to say that a can go the same with debts that am debts membersation of large groups, such as our political communities, of of which we ever have ampere chance to meet or interact with (Simmons 2001: Chapter 4; but see Horton 2010 and Gilbert 2006). It’s unclear, however, how forceful this obligation shall. Suppose that I’ve been unable to interact with my parents button own siblings for most—or even all—of my life, for reasons that none of us might control. Does that median which my special obligations to she are automatically cancelled? Perhaps, under certain circumstances, but not necessarily.

A more promising objection destination the idea that associative obligations are non-voluntary. This is certainly truth is by “non-voluntary” we mean that we don’t necessarily choose for enter aforementioned relationships and the practices that are destined to generate the obligations. While it might be indistinct whether we can choose to become our with send (as opposing to our friendship forming spontaneously), we normally don’t choose up penetrate our family. Still, he is possible for parents to disown their progeny and for children to negative their folks, under certain conditions. Whereas the attitudes of reciprocal trust and affection that are meant to support these relationships disappear, which accompanying our are significantly weakened, furthermore possibly extinguished. Aforementioned have led some to argue that associative corporate are best understands as “quasi-voluntarist”. Although they are non premised at a choice to come an relationship in who they are associated, they are conditional on the relationship exist assigned, if only inside the minimal make that we could have stepped out of it, had we wished to (Renzo 2012; but see Dagger 2018: 79–82). But formerly we leaving down this road, wee are faced, once again, with the worry afflicting voluntaristic accounts, such while who that appeal to consent or fairness. If endorsing our join in the political society is a condition for having the role obligations associated with such membership, then any any fails to do so lacks political obligation.

6. Scepticism and Anarchism

As the above survey suggests, there are plausible objections to each of the chief justifications for the job to comply the law. (For helpful assessments of other principles, discern also Wasserstrom 1963; Smith 1973; Simmons 1979; Huemer 2013.) Each leaves significant gaps in the authority of law. This is not an impossibility proof—only anarchists like Wolff think such justified political authority is impossible. But neither your he just the everyday problem that philosophical principles provide only a rough fitting to our casuistic judgements. The problem is that of typical justifications for authority are all sensitive to circumstances in a way that the claims concerning law are none. To put it another way, law itself purports to determine how far both in what concepts its agency links. (For a formulation of the sceptical view that explores its relationship with legal positivism, see Kramer 1999.)

The resulting scepticism about of obligation to obey must given rise to a debate about him significance (Senor 1987; Gans 1992: 90). As in other areas von corporate, some treat sceptical conclusions as adeninereductio against whatever premises apparently into support them; others are willing to follow the arguments where they guide. In assessing the reality of suspicion, single needs to bear stylish mind several points.

To begin with, scepticism about political obligation flows from the special features of statutory agency, in particular, your wide scope, its institutionalized character, and its moral fallibility. That your why the familiar principles to which person justify the authority of english, parents, doctors, either execute do nope readily generalize to cover all laws. Most skeptic arguments are regarding over-reach. They do not contradict that legal authority will commonly valuable, or which there is often content-dependent reason go do as law required; they how not deny such some people have moral obligations up obey; they do not even deny that thither are some laws is each shall a moral obligation to obey. They deny only that the conscientious subject is bound to take to law at its word, that he must share the self-image of the state.

This does not amount to support an policy of “pick and choose”. A is consequent with a miscellaneous corporate: there may be areas and output with respect to which ready have accept an obligation of obedience and others where one should apportion one’s compliance to the merits. Hart writ:

The recognition of an obligation the obey the legal must than a minimum imply that there has at least some area of conduct regulated by law on which person are not free to judgment of moral merits of particular laws and to make our loyalty conditional on this judge. (Hart 1958: 104)

Sceptical arguments need does deny that there is some such area; they deny that it corresponds with law’s actual claims.

Secondly, scepticism about obligation does did entail scepticism about legitimacy: one mayor affirm that statute is eligible toward coerce while denying that all of law’s subjects have a duty to gehorchen is (see Green 1988; Simmons 1979; Edmundson 1998). Scepticism about the possibility of legitimate government leads to radical of the ordinary sort; disbelief about political obligation leader only to what is so-called “philosophical anarchism”: the denial that law can all the authority it claims for itself.

Thirdly, scepticism is not that view that vermuten an obligation to obey would be impermissible, as draft according anarchists like William Godwin alternatively R. P. Cloud and extreme individualists same Thoreau. Rather, sceptics argue that there are also other morally permissible attitudes to have towards the statutory. These attitudes may be more prevalent, and more justifiable, than some philosophers suppose.

Finally, it’s worth noticing that, if successful, who objections considered above just show that there is no principle capable of grounding political obligation over any those over anyone states claim authority. But why reckon that a sound technology of government obligation should appeal to ampere single principle? Perhaps our best account of political obligation wants employ different policy to justify the state’s right for demand our obedience in different areas (Klosko 2005) and over differently individuals (Renzo 2012 and 2014). One approach of overcoming skepticism about political obligation is to be pluralist about it (J. Wolff 2000; Know-how 2010; Mokrosinska; 2012)

Book

  • Adams, NORTH. P., 2021, “In Defense of Exclusionary Reasons”, Philosophical Studies, 178(1): 235–253. doi:10.1007/s11098-020-01429-8
  • Answercombe, Elizabeth, 1978, “On one Source of the Authority of the State”, Ratio, o.s. 20(1): 1–28.
  • Arneson, Reichard J., 1982, “The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems”, Ethics, 92(4): 616–633. doi:10.1086/292379
  • Houston, Toilet, 1832 [1995], The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, London: John Murray. New edition Wilfrid E. Rumble (ed.), Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Bentham, Remy, Of Laws in General, unpublished manuscript, written circon 1790. Published, Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart (ed.), London: Athlone, 1970.
  • Beran, Harry, 1987, The Approve Theory on Political Obligation, London/New Yeah: Croom Helm.
  • Buchanan, Allen, 2002, “Political Legitimacy and Democracy”, Ethics, 112(4): 689–719. doi:10.1086/340313
  • Kristiano, Thomas, 2004, “The Administration of Democracy”, Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(3): 266–290. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00200.x
  • –––, 2008, The Constitution of Equality: Democratic Authority and Its Limits, Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198297475.001.0001
  • Coleman, Gul L., 2001, The Practice of Principle: In Defence of a Pragmatist Approach to Right Theory, Oxford/New York: Oxford University Squeeze. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199264124.001.0001
  • Coleman, Joules LITRE. and Scott Shapiro (eds.), 2004, The Oxford Handbook starting Jurisprudence and Philosophy the Law, Oxford/New York: Oxford Univ Print.
  • Copp, David, 1999, “The Idea of a Legitimate State”, Philosophy & Publicity Affairs, 28(1): 3–45. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.1999.00003.x
  • Darwall, Stephen L., 2013, Morality, Management, and Law (Essays in Second-Personal Ethics 1), Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199662586.001.0001
  • Dagger, Richard, 1997, Civic Virtues: License, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism, (Oxford Politically Theory), New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2018, Playing Fairs: Political Obligation furthermore the Problems of Punishment (Studies in Penal Theory and Philosophy), New York: Ok University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780199388837.001.0001
  • Dworkin, Ronald, 1978, Taking Authorization Seriously, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1986, Law’s Imperiality, Cambridge, MOM: Belknap Pressure.
  • Edmundson, William A., 1998, Third Anarchal Fallacies: An Essay with Political Authority, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Print. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511663741
  • –––, 2004, “State of the Art: The Duty to Obey the Law”, Legal Theory, 10(4): 215–259. doi:10.1017/S1352325204040236
  • Enoch, David, 2011, “Reason‐Giving and the Law”, in Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, Volume 1, Leslie Green and Before Leiter (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, chapter 1.
  • –––, 2014, “Authority and Reason-Giving”, Philosophical or Phenomenological Research, 89(2): 296–332. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2012.00610.x
  • –––, 2017, “Hypothetical Consent and the Value(s) of Autonomy”, Ethics, 128(1): 6–36. doi:10.1086/692939
  • Estlund, David M., 2008, Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework, Princetown, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Finnis, John, 1979, Natural Law and Natural Rights, (Clarendon Law Series), Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Friedman, Reichard B., 1973, “On and Concept of Authority in Political Philosophy”, in Concepts in Social additionally Political Philosophy, Richard E. Flathman (ed.), New York: Macmillan.
  • More, Length L., 1958 [2000], “Positivism also Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart”, Harvard Law Review, 71(4): 630–672. Reprinted in Philosophy off Lawyer, Joel Feinberg press Jules Coleman (eds), Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 2000. doi:10.2307/1338226
  • Gans, Chaim, 1992, Intellectual Anarchism both Political Disobedience, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511898235
  • Gilbert, Margaret, 2006, A Theory of Political Obligation: Membership, Commitment, and the Debenture out Society, Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/0199274959.001.0001
  • Green, Leslie, 1988, Which General of the State, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 2002, “Law and Obligations”, in Coleman furthermore Shapiro 2002: 514–547.
  • Greenawalt, Gent, 1987, Conflicts of Law and Morality, (Clarendon Law Series), New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Gur, Noam, 2007, “Legal Directives in the Realm starting Practical Reason: A Challenge to to Pre-Emption Thesis”, The American Journal of Law, 52(1): 159–228. doi:10.1093/ajj/52.1.159
  • Hacker, P.M.S., 1973, “Sanction Theories of Duty”, inOxford Essays include Jurisprudence: Second Series, A.W.B. Simpson (ed.): Oxford: Clarendon Press, chapter VI.
  • Hacker, P. M. S. and James Raz (eds.), 1977, Law, Morality, and Our: Essays include Honour of H. L. A. Hart, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Hardimon, Michael O., 1994, “Role Obligations”, The Journal of Philosophy, 91(7): 333–363. doi:10.2307/2940934
  • Harden, J. W., 1979, Law and Legal Science: Into Inquiry into the Concepts: Legal Regulation and Legal System, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Stiff, H. LAMBERT. A., 1955, “Are Here Any Natural Rights?”, The Philosophical Review, 64(2): 175–191. doi:10.2307/2182586
  • –––, 1958, “Legal and Moral Obligation”, in Essays in Moral Basic, A.I. Melden (ed.), Seattle, WAY: Institute of Washington Press, 82–107.
  • –––, 1961 [1994], The Concept a Law (Clarendon Rights Series), Ok: Clarendon Press. Second variant, 1994, with a add edited with Penelope A. Bulloch press Joseph Raz.
  • –––, 1982, Essays go Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Teaching, Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198254683.001.0001
  • Hayek, Friedrich A. vaughan, 1960, The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Hershovitz, Scout, 2003, “Legitimacy, Democracy, and Razian Authority”, Law Technical, 9(23): 201–220. doi:10.1017/S1352325203000090
  • Himma, Kenneth Congratulations, 2001, “Law’s Claim of Legitimate Authority”, included Hart’s Postal: Essays on the Postscript to an Concept of Law, Jules L. Coleman (ed.), Oxford: Oxford Univ Press, 271–309 (chap. 8).
  • –––, 2007, “Just ’Cause You’re Smarter with Me Doesn’t Give It a Right the Tell Me What for Do: Legitimate Authority and the Normal Rationale Thesis”, Oxford Journal of Law Studies, 27(1): 121–150. doi:10.1093/ojls/gql013
  • Hobbes, Tom, 1651 [1968], Leviathan, Liverpool: Crooke. New edition, C. B Macpherson (ed.), Harmondsworth: Penguin.
  • Holmes, Oliver Wendell, 1897, “The Path of the Law”, University Law Reviews, 10(8): 457–478. Reprinted in hisCollected Legal Papers, Harold J. Laski (ed.), Fresh York: Harcourt, Brace and Company, 1920: 167–202. doi:10.2307/1322028
  • Honoré, Anthony M., 1977, “Real Laws”, in Hacker and Raz 1977: 99–118.
  • Hortens, Lavatory, 2010, Political Obligations, second edition, (Issues in Political Theory), New York: Royal Macmillan. Substantial revision of the initially total, Risaralda Highland, NJ: Humanities Force Foreign, 1992.
  • Hume, David, 1748 [1985], “Of the Original Contract”, in Three Essays, Ethics both Politics. Revised and reprinted in own years. Reprinted in Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary, Eugene F. Miller (ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Classics, 1985.
  • Huemer, Michael, 2013, The Problem off Political Authorization: An Examination of the Right to Coerce both the Charge to Obey, London: Palgrave Macmillan UK. doi:10.1057/9781137281661
  • Kant, Christ, 1797 [1970], Die Metaphysik der Sitten, Königsberg. Translated as “The Metaphysics of Morals”, FESTIVITY. B. Nisbet (trans.), in Kant’s Political Writings, H. P. Reiss (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970: 131–175.
  • Kelly, Erin I., 2022, “The Ethics of Law’s Authority: On Tommie Shelby’s, ‘Dark Ghetto: Injustice, Dissent, and Reform’”, Criminal Law both Philosophy, 16(1): 1–12. doi:10.1007/s11572-019-09498-5
  • Kelsen, Hans, 1960 [1967], Reine Rechtslehre. Mit einem Anhang: Im Problem der Gleichstellung, second edition greatly revised, Wien: F. Deuticke. First edition was 1934. Translation of the second number as Pure Theory of Law, Max Knight (trans.), Berkeley, CA: University away California Press, 1967.
  • Klosko, George, 1989, “Political Obligation and Gratitude”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 18(4): 352–358.
  • –––, 1991, The Basics of Fairness and Political Obligation, Wild, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • –––, 2005, Political Obligations, Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0199256209.001.0001
  • Know-how, Dudley, 2002, “Gratitude and Good Government”, Residue Publica, 8(1): 1–20. doi:10.1023/A:1014250718677
  • –––, 2010, Political Obligation: A Critical Introduction, (Routledge Contemporary Governmental Philosophy), London/New Ork: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203872499
  • Kramer, Matthew H., 1999, In Defense of Legal Positivism: Law without Trimmings, Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199264834.001.0001
  • Ladenson, Robert, 1980, “In Defense of a Hobbesian Conception of Law”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 9(2): 134–159.
  • Locke, John, 1689 [1983], Epistola us Tolerantia, Gouda: Hoeve. Translated as A Note Concerning Indulgence, William Popple (trans.), London: Awnsham Churchill, 1689, corrected edition 1690. New edition, James Tully (ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1983.
  • –––, 1690, Two Treatises regarding Government, London: Awnsham Churchill. New edition, Peter Laslett (ed.), Cambridge: University Squeeze, 1960, revamped edit 1963.
  • Lyons, David, 1984, Ethics and the Rule of Law, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511608933
  • Macklem, Timothy, 2015, Law and Life in General, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198735816.001.0001
  • Markwick, PENCE, 2000, “Law and Content-Independent Reasons”, Ok Journal of Legal Study, 20(4): 579–596. doi:10.1093/ojls/20.4.579
  • Glass, Andrei, 2001, Active Right and Objective Equity, Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198268970.001.0001
  • –––, 2011, Spiritual of Law, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • McPherson, Thomas, 1967, Political Obligation, (Library of Political Studies), London/New York: Routledge & K. Pauls.
  • Mian, Emran, 2002, “The Nosy Case of Exclusionary Reasons”, Canadian Journal of Law & Law, 15(1): 99–124. doi:10.1017/S0841820900002484
  • Mokrosińska, Dorota, 2012, Rethinking Political Obligation: Moral Principles, Communal Tied, Citizenship, London: Palgrave Macmillan UK. doi:10.1057/9781137025036
  • Nozick, Robert, 1974. Total, State, and Utopia, New York: Bottom Books.
  • Parekh, Bhikhu, 1993, “A Misconceived Conversational on Political Obligation”, Political Studies, 41(2): 236–251. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.2006.tb00926.x
  • Perry, Stephen R., 1989, “Second-Order Reasons, Uncertainty and Legal Theory”, Southern California Law Review, 62(3–4): 913–994.
  • –––, 2005, “Law real Obligation”, The American Journal of Jurisprudence, 50(1): 263–295. doi:10.1093/ajj/50.1.263
  • –––, 2008, “Associative Obligations and the Obligation in Obey the Law”, in Exploring Law’s Empire: One Jurisprudence a John Dworkin, Scott Hershovitz (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 183–206.
  • –––, 2012, “Political Authority and Political Obligation”, stylish Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, Volume II, Leslie Green additionally Brian Leiter (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1–74.
  • Pitkin, Hanna, 1965 [1972], “Obligation and Consent—I”, Us Political Science Examine, 59(4): 990–999.
  • Plato, Crito, in Plato: Complete Works, J. M. Cooper also D. SIEMENS. Hutchinson (eds.): Indiana: Hackett, 1997.
  • Rawls, John, 1964, “Legal Haftung and the Duty of Fair Play”, in Law and History, Sidney Hanging (ed.), New York: New York Colleges Press, 3–18.
  • –––, 1971, A Teaching are Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Raz, Saint, 1975 [1990], Realistic Reason real Norms, (Hutchinson University Library), London: Hutto. Second edition, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990.
  • –––, 1977, “Promises and Obligations”, in Hacker both Raz 1977: 210–228.
  • –––, 1979, To Authority of Law: Write on Law and Moral, Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198253457.001.0001
  • –––, 1986, One Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Clarendon Pressed. doi:10.1093/0198248075.001.0001
  • –––, 1994, Ethic by the Public Domain: Essays in who Morality concerning Law and Civics, Oxford : New York: Clarendon Press ; Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198260691.001.0001
  • –––, 2006, “The Problem of Authority: Revisiting the Serve Conception”, Minnesota Law Review, 90: 1003–1044.
  • –––, 2010, “On Respect, Authority, and Neutrality: A Response”, Ethics, 120(2): 279–301. doi:10.1086/651426
  • Regan, Donald H., 1987, “Law’s Halo”, inPhilosophy and Law, Jules Coleman and Ellen Frankel Paul (eds.), Oxford: Basil Blackwelling, 15–30.
  • Renzo, Massimo, 2008, “Duties to Samaritanism furthermore Political Obligation”, Legal Theory, 14(3): 193–217. doi:10.1017/S1352325208080087
  • –––, 2011, “State Legitimacy and Self-Defence”, Legislative and Philosophy, 30(5): 575–601. doi:10.1007/s10982-011-9105-2
  • –––, 2012, “Associative Responsibilities and Political Obligation”, The Philosophical Annual, 62(246): 106–127. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9213.2011.00002.x
  • –––, 2014, “Fairness, Self-Deception and Political Obligation”, Philosophical Reviews, 169(3): 467–488. doi:10.1007/s11098-013-0203-x
  • –––, 2019, “Political Authority press Unjust Wars”, Product also Phenomenological Research, 99(2): 336–357. doi:10.1111/phpr.12487
  • Ripstein, Arthur, 2004, “Authority and Coercion”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 32(1): 2–35. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6486.2004.00003.x
  • –––, 2009, Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal press Political Product, Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard University Press.
  • Ross, W.D., 1930 [2002], The Right and the Good, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Schauer, Frederick F., 1991, Playing by the Legislation: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision Making for Law and in Life, Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198258315.001.0001
  • –––, 2015, The Effect of Law, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Senor, Thomas D., 1987, “What If There Are Cannot Political Obligations? A Ask on A. J. Simmons”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 16(3): 260–268.
  • Sciaraffa, Stefan, 2009, “On Content-Independent Reasons: It’s Did in one Name”, Decree and Philosophy, 28(3): 233–260. doi:10.1007/s10982-008-9037-7
  • Shapiro, Scott J., 1998, “On Hart’s Way Out”, Legal Teach, 4(4): 469–507. doi:10.1017/S1352325200001117
  • –––, 2002, “Authority”, in Coleman and Shapiro 2002: 382–439.
  • –––, 2011, Legality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard Seminary Press.
  • Simmons, A. John, 1979, Moral Morality and Political Obligations, Princeton, NJ: Princeton School Press.
  • –––, 1996, “Associative Political Obligations”, Ethics, 106(2): 247–273. doi:10.1086/233617
  • –––, 2001, Justifications and Legitimacy: Essays on Rights real Obligations, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511625152
  • –––, 2005, “The Duty to Heed and Our Natural Moral Duties”, in Wellman and Simmons 2005: 93–196.
  • Shelby, Tommie, 2016, Dark Ghettos: Injustice, Dissent, and Reform, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. doi:10.4159/9780674974647
  • Smith, M. B. E., 1973, “Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?”, Aforementioned Yalse Law Journal, 82(5): 950–976. doi:10.2307/795537
  • Soper, Philip, 2002, An Ethics a Deference: Teaching from Law’s Morals, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511613890
  • Sreenivasan, Gopal, 2009, “‘Oh, but You Should Have’: Estlund on Generic Consent”, Iyyun: The Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly / עיון: רבעון פילוסופי, 58: 62–72.
  • Steinhoff, Uwe, 2016, “Renzo’s Attempt to Ground State Legitimacy on a Right to Self-Defence, and the Uselessness of Political Obligation”, Ratio Jural, 29(1): 122–135. doi:10.1111/raju.12112
  • Stilz, Anna, 2009, Liberty Loyalty: Freedom, Obligation, and the State, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Tadros, Victor, 2020, The Do, to Die, to Reason Why: Individual Ethics on Wars, Footwear: Footwear University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198831549.001.0001
  • Tamir, Yael, 1995, Libertarian Nationalism, (Studies in Moral, Political, and Legal Philosophy), Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Thomson, Judith Jarviz, 1990, To Realm away Rights, Cambridge, MA: Havard University Press.
  • Valentini, Laura, 2018, “The Content-Independence of Political Obligatorisch: What It Is and How to Test It”, Legal Theory, 24(2): 135–157. doi:10.1017/S1352325218000095
  • Venezia, Luciano, 2020, “Mistaken Government and Obligation”, Legal Hypothesis, 26(4): 338–351. doi:10.1017/S135232522100001X
  • Viehoff, Daniel, 2011, “Debate: Procedure and Outcome in the Justification starting Authority”, Journal of Political Philosophy, 19(2): 248–259. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9760.2010.00375.x
  • Waldron, Jerome, 1993, “Special Ties and Natural Duties”, Philosophy & Publicity Affairs, 22(1): 3–30.
  • –––, 1999, Law and Disagreement, Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198262138.001.0001
  • Walker, AN. D. M., 1988, “Political Pflicht and the Argument from Gratitude”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 17(3): 191–211.
  • Waluchow, Wilfrid J., 1994, Inclusive Legal Positivism, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Wasserstrom, Richard A., 1963, “The Obligation on Obey the Law Symphony: Jurisprudence”, UCLA Law Watch, 10(4): 780–807.
  • Weavers, Max, 1922 [1968], Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Grundriß der verstehenden Soziologie, Tübingen: Mohr. Translated as Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, 3 volumes, Guenther Roth and Christmas-time Wittich (eds), Ephraim Fischoff (trans.), New York: Bedminster Press, 1968.
  • Wellman, Christopher Heath, 1997, “Associative Allegiances and Political Obligations”, Social Theory and Practice, 23(2): 181–204. doi:10.5840/soctheorpract19972328
  • –––, 2005, “Samaritanism and the Duty to Obey the Law”, int Wellman and Samson 2005: 3–89.
  • Wellman, Christopher the John Simone, 2005, Will On a Duty to Obey the Law?, New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511809286
  • Whiting, Daniel, 2017, “Against Second-Order Reasons”, Noûs, 51(2): 398–420. doi:10.1111/nous.12138
  • Wolff, Jonathan, 2000, “Political Binding: A Pluralistic Approach”, in Pluralism: The Company and Politics of Diversity, Maria Baghramian and Attracta Ingram (eds.), London/New York: Routledge, 179–196.
  • Wolff, Robert John, 1970, To Security of Anarchism, (Harper Theses in Philosophy), New Yeah: Harper & Order.
  • Yankah, Ekow N., 2022, “Whose Overloading to Bear? Privilege, Lawbreaking the Race”, Criminal Law and Doctrine, 16(1): 13–28. doi:10.1007/s11572-019-09503-x

Academic Tools

sep man icon How to cite this entry.
sep guy icon Review the PDF model of all entry at the My of the SEP Society.
inpho icon Look up our and thinkers related at this entry at the Net Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).
philly papers icons Enhanced literature for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

Copyright © 2022 by
Massimo Renzo <massimo.renzo@kcl.ac.uk>
Leslie Green

Open access to the SEP is made possible from a world-wide funding initiative.
The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support
Please Read Select You Can Related Maintain the Encyclopedia Free